[I wrote the following essay in November 2006 as a companion to the
work of John Joe Lakers, O.F.M., who uses his background in linguistic
philosophy to argue for a moral discourse different from the one commonly
assumed by Catholic authors.]
In
his now well-known lecture in September 2006 to an assembly of German academics at
the University of Regensburg, Pope Benedict XV repeated a hope often voiced by
his predecessor, John Paul II. The hope is that the Church be able to speak to
present-day secular culture in new ways. In Benedict’s words, “. . .if reason
and faith come together in a new way, . . . only thus do we become capable of
that genuine dialogue of cultures and religions so urgently needed today.”
Public reaction to the lecture centered on Benedict’s use of a quotation
from a fourteenth century Byzantine emperor. The quotation accused Islam of
being a religion of violence. The public reaction to the Pope’s quotation
drowned out any discussion of the claims he made about reason and faith. However,
Benedict chose to speak in an academic environment, and as an academic
accustomed to discourse in such environments, I want to offer a critical
reaction.
Philosophical thinking since the time of Thomas Aquinas has moved in
directions that call Aquinas’s synthesis into question. As Benedict himself
noted in his lecture, the Franciscan John Duns Scotus already in the 14th
century disagreed with Aquinas. Subsequent centuries saw Catholic philosophy
develop in many directions away from Aquinas. It was only in the late 19th
century that Pope Leo XIII raised Aquinas up as a model for Catholic
philosophy, and baptized Aquinas’s thought as THE way Catholics ought to
approach philosophy. Such a baptism hardly fits comfortably with the claim that
philosophy should proceed totally without the light of revelation, in order
that revelation might better be understood. The claim also sat uncomfortably
with my own Franciscan seminary educators, who based their teaching on Scotus
and his 14th century pupil, William of Ockham.
Leo’s baptism of Aquinas gave rise to the movement called “neo-scholasticism,”
a movement that virtually disappeared after 1960. Secular philosophy, beginning
already in the 17th century with René Descartes and Thomas Hobbes, also moved
away from medieval scholasticism. Modern thought has been shaped not only by
those two figures, but also by writers such as Jean Jacques Rousseau, John
Locke, Emmanuel Kant, Georg Hegel, Edmund Husserl, and Martin Heidegger. In social
science, Karl Marx, Max Weber, Emile Durkheim, George Herbert Mead, Sigmund
Freud, Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann, and the rest of the immense literature
in sociology and psychology have implications for our thinking about the human
person. Analytic philosophy, focusing on analysis of language, and the still
more recent movement called postmodernism require response from thinking
Catholics, and a response based on more than the thinking of one medieval
philosopher-theologian who was known in his day for the courage to enter
dialogue with the “pagan” philosophers, Plato and Aristotle.
Any
true dialogue with modern culture must be willing to include any and all
secular authors in the conversation. The fact that Benedict ended his consideration
of post-Aquinas authors with Duns Scotus suggests an ignorance of the culture
that Benedict wants to engage. According to Lakers, Scotus was struggling to
deal with problems not adequately dealt with by his predecessors. He was not
able to reach a solution to those problems, but his struggle led to later
developments that were not, as Benedict claims, sad deviations from a search
for a truth already stated by Aquinas. The crux of the matter lies in the
meanings of the concept of “reason.” Benedict wants to claim that “reason” must
co-exist with faith (a point important to make in cultures where religious
fundamentalism is increasing), and that reason is incompatible with violence.
However, he goes on to say that “reason” means “Greek reason,” reason as enunciated
by, Plato, Aristotle, and Aquinas. That reason must co-exist with faith has
been a traditional Catholic position. That reason means Greek reason is, in
today's world, inexcusably ethnocentric. That Greek reason means reason as
enunciated by Plato, Aristotle, and Aquinas is not only ethnocentric but
disregards over seven subsequent centuries of philosophical tradition.
However, Lakers makes a deeper critique of Benedict's claim. According
to him, postmodernist authors claim that “reason” is a fictitious term. That
is, to use the concept of reason is to create a fictitious narrative, whose
effect is to shut down further conversation.
“Shutting
down conversation” may seem to be an overstatement. No one today wants to be accused
of doing that. But when authors claim that a statement is based on reason, the
reader has only two choices: reject the claim, or accept the claim and fall
silent.
An
example from present-day politics illustrates the point. Catholic pro-life
theologians claim that their position on abortion law is based not on religious
or denominational belief but on “natural law.” The term “natural law,” which is
regarded by almost all social scientists as incompatible with a scientific
outlook, creates a claim that an argument is based on reason. Having made that
claim, pro-life politicians can only move to raw political power, claiming
that, as citizens of a democracy, they have the right to try to influence
public policy. I do not dispute the right of anyone to try to influence public
policy. What I do dispute is the claim that the grounds for the pro-life
position are self-evident, based on reason, and can only be rejected by people
who are in bad faith.
One
could make a convincing argument against the pro-life political stance on the
basis of the traditional neo-scholastic distinction between what can be known
by reason without the aid of revelation, and what can be known only through
revelation. For example, I may accept on faith the Church teaching that the
human person is present from the first moment of conception. But I reject the
claim that such a teaching can be known from reason without the aid of
revelation. If the Church in this country were to acknowledge that its claim
about personhood is not known by reason alone, it would be forced to quit
accusing its opponents of bad faith, and would have to enter into discussion
with them on the basis of reasoned discourse, all the while recommending that
Catholics be guided by the official teaching.
The
claim that “reason” is a fiction implies a much deeper problem. At first glance
it would seem to open moral discourse up to total relativism. Lakers argues
that it does not. His argument requires an analysis of the nature of moral
discourse, of the way that human beings use language to make moral claims on
one another. Any moral claim, he says, is ultimately grounded in one of two
metaphors: the metaphor of power and judgment, or the metaphor of intimacy.
The
metaphor of power and judgment assumes that a competent judge can declare a
particular behavior to be wrong, and the individual who practices it must be
punished. The alternate way is to assume that human beings relate to one
another in the hope of realizing a life lived more fully. Lakers argues that
such a full life can come only from intimacy, which he defines as involvement
characterized by passion, respect, vulnerability, and faithfulness. The use of
a metaphor of intimacy does not result in purely random outcomes. Those four
criteria are demanding. But they do not settle for all times and places the
course of action that the individual should pursue.
The
first reaction of Church teachers will certainly be that Lakers’s position is “situational” ethics, condemned by the magisterium decades
ago. Lakers too rejects situational ethics, arguing that it is just another
appeal to “reason,” but an appeal that washes out most of the humanly
significant aspects of interpersonal behavior. Since we are dealing with
philosophy here, not theology, I cannot reject Lakers's ethics simply on the
grounds that the magisterium has condemned it. I will need to know why it is to
be condemned, and whether the magisterium has listened to my position. I will
relate to the magisterium from a metaphor of intimacy, and I will expect it to
relate the same way to me.
It
is true that we have not been doing things this way in the Catholic Church. But
we have changed a lot of things that were once thought to be self-evident. Both
Protestant and Roman Catholic theologians for centuries rejected as immoral the
practice of charging interest on loans. By the 18th century both Protestant and
Roman Catholic theologians, along with the magisterium, had found ways to
legitimize the practice. The legitimation occurred because generations of the
faithful acted on the basis of the intimate relationships that grow up between
living human beings and gradually shape a new moral consensus.
Today the behavior of Catholics in “western”
societies has moved vast distances from the positions claimed by the
magisterium. Poll data claim that over ninety percent of lay Catholics in the
United States reject papal teaching on contraception, and there is survey
evidence that nearly the same percentage of priests agree with the rejection.
Simply re-affirming the teaching will not be any more successful than John
XXIII’s decree (in the 1962 encyclical Veterum
Sapientiae) that Latin should henceforth be the language of all philosophical
and theological teaching in all Catholic seminaries throughout the world. Such
behavior of the faithful is not always, as some Churchmen would claim, a
symptom of a widespread loss of faith. Traditional theology referred to it as
the sensus fidelium, the “sentiment of the faithful.”
The
claim that western societies are hopelessly corrupted by secularism, and that
the future of the Church lies in Africa, Asia, and Latin America, is hardly a
courageous confronting of the challenges posed by “modernity.” What will happen
if and when the faithful in those regions acquire the affluence that
characterizes western societies? The lion must be bearded in its den. If the
Church cannot construct an argument for its moral positions that can at least
dialogue with western secular cultures, it will have abandoned its claim that
truth is one--that faith must co-exist with “reason.”
In
short, Lakers argues, the postmodernist critique of “reason” requires that
morality be grounded in something other than the traditional moral claim that
certain practices are intrinsically immoral and that their immorality can be
known by reason alone. Using his background in linguistic philosophy, he builds
an argument based on the metaphor of intimacy. Those behaviors which grow out
of the metaphor of intimacy are moral; those which do not are immoral. This
sounds very much like Paul's argument that the Law cannot save, or the gospels'
statements that Jesus' central commandment is a commandment of love.
In
short, Catholic moral theology can no longer ground itself in the concept of “reason.”
It must embrace the much messier, but also the much more demanding, use of the
metaphor of intimacy in its moral discourse. Only through intimacy can human
persons achieve the “fullness of life” that Christians see as the promise made
to us by Jesus.